by Reetobrata Chatterjee
In the early 20th century, one of the greatest
mathematical minds of the time, David Hilbert, posed 23 problems to the mathematical
world, which he hoped would be solved by the end of the century. These are
similar to the Millennium Problems.
He would have disappointed.
Hilbert’s Challenge was met by Kurt Gödel in 1931, in the
form of his incompleteness theorem, which is the actual topic of this essay. He
actually had 2 theorems, but the first one is considered more important and to
keep things (relatively) short, I’ll only discuss that.
David Hilbert |
He would have disappointed.
That may be a slight. Of the original 23 problems, called
Hilbert’s Problems, only four remain completely unresolved. Most are fully or
partially resolved, which is always good. The 2nd Problem is the one
this article is concerned with. It simply states:
“Prove that the axioms of arithmetic are consistent”
The axioms of any
branch of mathematics are the concepts which are accepted to be true without
any proof. Such fundamental “truths” are required in order to build onto more
complex things, known to us as theorems. These axioms are only accepted because
they are considered self-evident. This includes things like if a=b and b=c then
a=c. The only difference between this and the actual axiom is a bunch of
mathematical symbols.
Perhaps a more complex one is the axiom of induction. This
enables mathematicians to use proof by induction, a very powerful technique.
The outline, or lemma, goes as follows:
- Prove the “base case” – i.e. prove that for most basic instance, such as when x = 1, the results of the theorem match the calculated result.
- Assume that when x = k, the theorem holds true.
- Prove that if when x=k, the theorem holds true, then when x = k + 1, the theorem holds true as well.
- Induction Statement – If x = k => x = k + 1 and x = 1 is true, then x = 1 => x = 2 => x = 3 => … => for all x in the defined range.
Kurt Godel |
The statement of the theorem is:
“For any given axioms of arithmetic, the resulting system can either
consistent or complete, but not both.”
In simpler terms, this states that no matter which “truths”
you choose to accept in order to create the system we know as arithmetic
(currently Peano Arithmetic is used).
There will always be things that cannot be proved, if the axioms don’t contradict each other. This was akin to saying that a statement which could seem obvious, like 2 + 2 = 4, could not be proved from first principles by using the axioms. The other possibility (corresponding to the “incomplete” in the statement), is that a statement like 2 + 2 = 5, could be proved correct.
There will always be things that cannot be proved, if the axioms don’t contradict each other. This was akin to saying that a statement which could seem obvious, like 2 + 2 = 4, could not be proved from first principles by using the axioms. The other possibility (corresponding to the “incomplete” in the statement), is that a statement like 2 + 2 = 5, could be proved correct.
Mathematicians, being advocates of consistency decided to
take the first choice, have an incomplete system, as opposed to an inconsistent
one, because although it must be annoying to know that a proof they were
working on might not exist, it was better than one of their “correct” proofs
being obviously false.
This was a huge blow to other mathematicians working at this
time, because they were completely devoted to formalising the axioms of
arithmetic, like Hilbert had intended, only to have their work thrown out of
the window by a young American upstart who was only 25 at the time.
The proof is really complicated.
However, an analogy to the proof can be provided simply:
Imagine there is a printer, which will accepts and prints
documents. The one catch is that it will only print the document if the
statements it contains are true. If any statement is false, it won’t do
anything.
So for example if you put a statement saying “It’s going to
rain today” it would print it (since this is England).
However a statement like “Its 50C outside” would cause the
printer to do nothing (again because this is England).
It all seems fine up till now. There seems to be no
statements that will cause a paradox is there?
Let this Gödel Sentence be: “I can never print this”
This leads to a conundrum because if the printer prints
this, then the statement must be true. But then the printer couldn’t have
printed it. If the printer doesn’t print this, then the statement must be false
right? No.
If this was actually the case, the printer would probably
just explode or malfunction since then it would be out of order so the truth of
the statement would become undeterminable.
But mathematics cannot just explode or malfunction
(probably). So this leads to a paradox, which cannot exist either. This is what
Gödel proved in his work, that given a set of axioms of arithmetic, there is a
counterpart of “I can never print this”, which the fabric of mathematics cannot
take.
In conclusion, this theorem shook mathematics and I would
consider it one of the most significant of all time, alongside the likes of
calculus and Pythagoras’ Theorem, purely because it shows that even the most
simple systems in what’s considered the purest science is to some extent flawed
at its very core.
Comments
Post a Comment
Comments with names are more likely to be published.